The article Simpler, Easier! claims it could be possible to encode dependent type systems even without the presence of "Pi" - that is, you could reuse the "Lam" constructor for it. But how can that be true, if "Pi" and "Lam" are treated differently in some cases?
Moreover, could "Star" be removed? I think you could replace all occurrences of it by "λ x . x" (id).
What is COC meaning? COC or the Cycles Of Concentration is an abbreviation, used when talking about cooling water or cooling tower water. The COC specifies, how often a fresh water added into the loop, can be used or pumped around, before the water has to blown down or bleed off from the cooling tower.
Real-time object detection is the task of doing object detection in real-time with fast inference while maintaining a base level of accuracy. ( Image credit: CenterNet )
Blowdown: When water evaporates from the tower, dissolved solids (such as calcium, magnesium, chloride, and silica) remain in the recirculating water. As more water evaporates, the concentration of dissolved solids increases. If the concentration gets too high, the solids can cause scale to form within the system.
That's just overloading like (a, b)
in Haskell: it can be both a type and a value. You can use the same binder for Π
and λ
and typechecker will decide from the context which one you mean. If you typecheck one binder against another, then the former is λ
and the latter is Π
— and that's why you can't unambiguously replace *
with λ x . x
— because then the former binder could be Π
and the latter is *
(*
as a binder doesn't make any sense to me). There is a bigger problem with ∀ = λ
and * = λ x . x
: by transitivity * = ∀ x . x
, which is a common way to postulate False
— this type must be uninhabited in a sound system, so you won't have any types at all.
There was a recent thread on Coq-club "Similarities between forall and fun" (gmane.org gives me "No such message", is it just me?), here are some excerpts:
Dominic Mulligan:
And here is another with a small bibliography pointing to similar work:
http://www.macs.hw.ac.uk/~fairouz/forest/papers/journals-publications/jfp05.pdf
Ironically, according to that paper Coquand first presented the Calculus of Constructions with a single, unified binder, following a convention established by De Bruijn in AutoMath.
Thorsten Altenkirch:
A function and its type are very different concepts even if they have some superficial syntactic similarity.
Especially for the newcomer this identification is very confusing and completely misleading. I do think that one should understand type theoretical concepts from what they mean and not how they look like.
Andreas Abel:
My student Matthias Benkard also worked on such a system, see "Type Checking without Types"
http://www.cse.chalmers.se/~abela/benkardThesis.pdf
Note that the system described at the first link has Π-reduction (i.e. you can apply pi-types just like lambdas) — your system will have it too, if you unify Π
and λ
internally (as opposed to syntactically). And the system described at the second link unifies types and values
One immediate consequence is the absence of any distinction between types and their inhabitants: Every value is a type containing itself and all of its parts; and conversely, every type is a composite value consisting of its inhabitants.
so there is really just one binder (except for let
and maybe fix
).
If you love us? You can donate to us via Paypal or buy me a coffee so we can maintain and grow! Thank you!
Donate Us With