forall n m : nat, exists q : nat, exists r : nat, n = q * m + r
q
and r
from values m
and n
.Fixpoint
and extract that. I want to note carefully that that task is not what I'm considering here.Is it even possible to extract the algorithm implicit in my proof to Haskell? If it is possible, how would it be done?
Thanks to Prof. Pierce's summer 2012 video 4.1 as Dan Feltey suggested, we see that the key is that the theorem to be extracted must provide a member of Type
rather than the usual kind of propositions, which is Prop
.
For the particular theorem the affected construct is the inductive Prop ex
and its notation exists
. Similarly to what Prof. Pierce has done, we can state our own alternate definitions ex_t
and exists_t
that replace occurrences of Prop
with occurrences of Type
.
Here is the usual redefinition of ex
and exists
similarly as they are defined in Coq's standard library.
Inductive ex (X:Type) (P : X->Prop) : Prop := ex_intro : forall (witness:X), P witness -> ex X P. Notation "'exists' x : X , p" := (ex _ (fun x:X => p)) (at level 200, x ident, right associativity) : type_scope.
Here are the alternate definitions.
Inductive ex_t (X:Type) (P : X->Type) : Type := ex_t_intro : forall (witness:X), P witness -> ex_t X P. Notation "'exists_t' x : X , p" := (ex_t _ (fun x:X => p)) (at level 200, x ident, right associativity) : type_scope.
Now, somewhat unfortunately, it is necessary to repeat both the statement and the proof of the theorem using these new definitions.
What in the world??
Why is it necessary to make a reiterated statement of the theorem and a reiterated proof of the theorem, that differ only by using an alternative definition of the quantifier??
I had hoped to use the existing theorem in
Prop
to prove the theorem over again inType
. That strategy fails when Coq rejects the proof tacticinversion
for aProp
in the environment when thatProp
usesexists
and the goal is aType
that usesexists_t
. Coq reports "Error: Inversion would require case analysis on sort Set which is not allowed for inductive definition ex." This behavior occurred in Coq 8.3. I am not certain that it still occurs in Coq 8.4.I think the need to repeat the proof is actually profound although I doubt that I personally am quite managing to perceive its profundity. It involves the facts that
Prop
is "impredicative" andType
is not impredicative, but rather, tacitly "stratified". Predicativity is (if I understand correctly) vulnerability to Russell's paradox that the set S of sets that are not members of themselves can neither be a member of S, nor a non-member of S.Type
avoids Russell's paradox by tacitly creating a sequence of higher types that contain lower types. Because Coq is drenched in the formulae-as-types interpretation of the Curry-Howard correspondence, and if I am getting this right, we can even understand stratification of types in Coq as a way to avoid Gödel incompleteness, the phenomenon that certain formulae express constraints on formulae such as themselves and thereby become unknowable as to their truth or falsehood.
Back on planet Earth, here is the repeated statement of the theorem using "exists_t".
Theorem divalg_t : forall n m : nat, exists_t q : nat, exists_t r : nat, n = plus (mult q m) r.
As I have omitted the proof of divalg
, I will also omit the proof of divalg_t
. I will only mention that we do have the good fortune that proof tactics including "exists" and "inversion" work just the same with our new definitions "ex_t" and "exists_t".
Finally, the extraction itself is accomplished easily.
Extraction Language Haskell. Extraction "divalg.hs" divalg_t.
The resulting Haskell file contains a number of definitions, the heart of which is the reasonably nice code, below. And I was only slightly hampered by my near-total ignorance of the Haskell programming language. Note that Ex_t_intro
creates a result whose type is Ex_t
; O
and S
are the zero and the successor function from Peano arithmetic; beq_nat
tests Peano numbers for equality; nat_rec
is a higher-order function that recurs over the function among its arguments. The definition of nat_rec
is not shown here. At any rate it is generated by Coq according to the inductive type "nat" that was defined in Coq.
divalg :: Nat -> Nat -> Ex_t Nat (Ex_t Nat ()) divalg n m = case m of { O -> Ex_t_intro O (Ex_t_intro n __); S m' -> nat_rec (Ex_t_intro O (Ex_t_intro O __)) (\n' iHn' -> case iHn' of { Ex_t_intro q' hq' -> case hq' of { Ex_t_intro r' _ -> let {k = beq_nat r' m'} in case k of { True -> Ex_t_intro (S q') (Ex_t_intro O __); False -> Ex_t_intro q' (Ex_t_intro (S r') __)}}}) n}
Update 2013-04-24: I know a bit more Haskell now. To assist others in reading the extracted code above, I'm presenting the following hand-rewritten code that I claim is equivalent and more readable. I'm also presenting the extracted definitions Nat, O, S, and nat_rec that I did not eliminate.
-- Extracted: Natural numbers (non-negative integers) -- in the manner in which Peano defined them. data Nat = O | S Nat deriving (Eq, Show) -- Extracted: General recursion over natural numbers, -- an interpretation of Nat in the manner of higher-order abstract syntax. nat_rec :: a1 -> (Nat -> a1 -> a1) -> Nat -> a1 nat_rec f f0 n = case n of { O -> f; S n0 -> f0 n0 (nat_rec f f0 n0)} -- Given non-negative integers n and m, produce (q, r) with n = q * m + r. divalg_t :: Nat -> Nat -> (Nat, Nat) divalg_t n O = (O, n) -- n/0: Define quotient 0, remainder n. divalg_t n (S m') = divpos n m' -- n/(S m') where -- Given non-negative integers n and m', -- and defining m = m' + 1, -- produce (q, r) with n = q * m + r -- so that q = floor (n / m) and r = n % m. divpos :: Nat -> Nat -> (Nat, Nat) divpos n m' = nat_rec (O, O) (incrDivMod m') n -- Given a non-negative integer m' and -- a pair of non-negative integers (q', r') with r <= m', -- and defining m = m' + 1, -- produce (q, r) with q*m + r = q'*m + r' + 1 and r <= m'. incrDivMod :: Nat -> Nat -> (Nat, Nat) -> (Nat, Nat) incrDivMod m' _ (q', r') | r' == m' = (S q', O) | otherwise = (q', S r')
If you love us? You can donate to us via Paypal or buy me a coffee so we can maintain and grow! Thank you!
Donate Us With