I am using the Coq Proof Assistant to implement a model of a (small) programming language (extending an implementation of Featherweight Java by Bruno De Fraine, Erik Ernst, Mario Südholt). One thing that keeps coming up when using the induction
tactic is how to preserve the information wrapped in type constructors.
I have a sub typing Prop implemented as
Inductive sub_type : typ -> typ -> Prop :=
| st_refl : forall t, sub_type t t
| st_trans : forall t1 t2 t3, sub_type t1 t2 -> sub_type t2 t3 -> sub_type t1 t3
| st_extends : forall C D,
extends C D ->
sub_type (c_typ C) (c_typ D).
Hint Constructors sub_type.
where extends
is the class extension mechanism as seen in Java, and typ
represents the two different kinds of types available,
Inductive typ : Set :=
| c_typ : cname -> typ
| r_typ : rname -> typ.
An example of where I would like type information to be preserved is when using the induction
tactic on a hypothesis like
H: sub_type (c_typ u) (c_typ v)
E.g. in
u : cname
v : cname
fsv : flds
H : sub_type (c_typ u) (c_typ v)
H0 : fields v fsv
============================
exists fs : flds, fields u (fsv ++ fs)
using induction H.
discards all information about u
and v
. The st_refl
case becomes
u : cname
v : cname
fsv : flds
t : typ
H0 : fields v fsv
============================
exists fs : flds, fields u (fsv ++ fs)
As you can see the information that u
and v
are related to the typ
constructors in H
, and thus to t
, is lost. What is worse is that due to this Coq is unable to see that u
and v
must in fact be the same in this case.
When using the inversion
tactic on H
Coq succeeds in seeing that u
and v
are the same. That tactic is not applicable here however, as I need the induction hypotheses that induction
generates to prove the st_trans
and st_extends
cases.
Is there a tactic that combines the best of inversion
and induction
to both generate induction hypotheses and derive equalities without destroying information about what is wrapped in the constructors? Alternatively, is there a way to manually derive the information I need? info inversion H
and info induction H
both show that a lot of transformations are applied automatically (especially with inversion
). These have led me to experiment with the change
tactic along with let ... in
construction, but without any progress.
Induction Cooktop Safety Because the surface of an induction stove or cooktop doesn't get hot, you—or your curious youngster—can touch it with your fingers without getting burned. This also means that if you splatter sauce onto the cooking surface, it won't burn, making cleanup easier.
Yes, induction cooktops do emit electromagnetic frequency radiation when used, and exposure to this radiation can be dangerous if not properly managed.
This is a general problem when you need to induct over a hypothesis with a dependent type (sub_type (c_typ u) (c_typ v)
) whose parameters have a particular structure (c_typ u
). There is a general trick, which is to selectively rewrite the structured parameter to a variable, keeping the equality in the environment.
set (t1 := c_typ u) in H; assert (Eq1 : t1 = c_typ u) by reflexivity; clearbody t1.
set (t2 := c_typ u) in H; assert (Eq2 : t2 = c_typ u) by reflexivity; clearbody t2.
induction H. (*often "; try subst" or "; try rewrite Eq1; try rewrite Eq2" *).
Since Coq 8.2, this common set-assert-clearbody pattern is performed by the built-in tactic remember term as ident in *goal_occurences*
.
Here's a silly lemma proved using this tactic.
Lemma subtype_r_left_equal :
forall r1 t2, sub_type (r_typ r1) t2 -> r_typ r1 = t2.
Proof.
intros.
remember (r_typ r1) as t1 in H.
induction H.
congruence.
solve [firstorder].
discriminate.
Qed.
Bonus tip (from experience, but it's been a while so I don't remember the details): when you're doing fairly syntactic reasoning on type systems (which tends to be the case when you do these kinds of mechanical proofs), it can be convenient to keep typing judgements in Set
. Think of typing derivations as objects you're reasoning about. I remember cases where it was convenient to introduce equalities on typing derivation, which doesn't always work with typing derivations in Prop
.
With your Problem.v
, here's a proof of the reflexivity case. For transitivity, I suspect your induction hypothesis isn't strong enough. This may be a byproduct of the way you simplified the problem, though transitivity often does require surprisingly involved induction hypotheses or lemmas.
Fact sub_type_fields: forall u v fsv,
sub_type (c_typ u) (c_typ v) -> fields v fsv ->
exists fs, fields u (fsv ++ fs).
Proof.
intros.
remember (c_typ u) as t1 in H.
remember (c_typ v) as t2 in H.
induction H.
(* case st_refl *)
assert (v = u). congruence. subst v t.
exists nil. rewrite <- app_nil_end. assumption.
(* case st_trans *)
subst t1 t3.
(* case st_extends *)
Admitted.
If you love us? You can donate to us via Paypal or buy me a coffee so we can maintain and grow! Thank you!
Donate Us With